Cognitive Architecture as Revolutionary Science
نویسندگان
چکیده
Many proposals for evaluating cognitive architectures rely partly on an analogy between cognitive science and other sciences. We therefore reflect on the relations between cognitive science, cognitive architectures and other sciences. Some important differences caution against the misguided use of some evaluation approaches. Some unique characteristics of human intelligence motivate the need for new approaches to evaluating cognitive architecture design. We briefly propose one such approach. In science there is a general expectation that when you do something, you have some way of showing that it has achieved your goal, that it is in some way valid. For example, when a theory generates predictions that other theories do not, then confirming these predictions is evidence it is true. Another way to support a theory is true is to prove theorems about some of its desired characteristics. These approaches successfully used by so many scientific communities that people naturally expect cognitive modelers to adopt them. This is based on a misunderstanding of both science and of the cognitive architecture approach. First, let us recall the distinction (Kuhn, 1970) between revolutionary science and normal science. These can be illustrated with an example. Many scientists working within the Newtonian framework accept Newton’s conception of space, time, inertia, mass and force and also accepted his three laws regarding the relations between these. Their work involves applying this apparatus to generate explanations or predictions of specific phenomena. They conduct experiments to confirm that the observations their work leads them to expect are indeed observed. If an experiment fails, they generally assume it is a problem with their application of the Newtonian framework instead of a flaw in the framework itself. Khun calls this normal science. He calls the project of developing a framework such as Newtonian physics, molecular biology or evolutionary biology revolutionary science. As Kuhn, Quine (1951) and others point out, one does not confirm or disconfirm a scientific framework with one or a small number of experiments. When a particular prediction of a framework fails, one normally first blames their application of the framework. For example, clouds and birds do not obviously obey Newton’s laws. Rather than rejecting Newtonian physics, one thinks very carefully about the specific forces involving cloud and bird motion and attempts to conceive of them so that they are consistent with Newton’s laws. When scientists accepting Newtoinan physics observed Uranus and Neptune’s orbits were not what they expected, they did not reject Newtonian physics but instead posited the existence of a large mass disturbing the orbit. This mass turned out to be Pluto. These examples illustrate that the observation-hypothesis-experiment caricature of the scientific method does not apply to developing a scientific framework. It is our thesis that developing cognitive architectures has some of the characteristics of revolutionary science and that developing models within a cognitive architecture has more of the characteristics of normal science. A cognitive architecture provides a basic computational framework for explaining and predicting human cognition. For example, in many architectures, rules, declarative memory and a process for using these to select actions function like the concepts of mass, inertia and Newton’s laws do in physics. They provide a basic framework for explaining and predicting a wide range of phenomena. Models of cognition in a particular situation are similar to explanations of specific physical phenomena in that they use the basic apparatus of the conceptual framework without disrupting it. The fact that cognitive architectures are more like a scientific framework than a specific explanation of a phenomena has several implications. First, just as specific experiments are not sufficient to evaluate scientific frameworks, cognitive architectures cannot be evaluated or compared merely by employing the traditional model fitting or hypothesis testing from experimental psychology. For example, when an ACT-R model makes an incorrect prediction it is more likely a problem with a production rule, parameter or declarative memory element in the model than the architectural framework of ACT-R itself. How then should cognitive architectures be evaluated? Typical standards used to evaluate other scientific frameworks are: Do they explain and predict a wide range of phenomena that were previously unexplained? Are they
منابع مشابه
The Impact of Architectural Competitions on the Improvement of the Post-Revolution Architecture in Iran
The 1979 Islamic Revolution of Iran is considered as a turning point in the contemporary architecture of the nation. There have been apexes to the eye catching architectural improvements in the three forthcoming decades after the revolution. One of the most effective isorganizing the contests in architectural that affairs has not only removed the recession in the field but has also discarded th...
متن کاملThe Future Prospects for Embodied Cognition
When all the data and arguments are in, will the recent flurry of work in embodied cognition deliver a revolutionary paradigm shift in the sciences and philosophy of mind? Or will it be a case of business as usual in the mind-targeting laboratories and armchairs around the globe? Or is the most likely outcome a reformist tweak in which embodied cognition research is recognized as making genuine...
متن کاملInterpreting Iranian Architecture in The Post-Revolutionary Period with Interaction Model of Tectonic and Stereotomic Theory Approaches
Since tectonic and stereotomic theories have neither been used systematically nor dealt with simultaneously for the interpretation of architecture, by explaining the theoretical position of critics and their thoughts, the process of their interaction will be more effective. The main questions asked is it possible to interpret architecture through the interaction of tectonic and stereotomical th...
متن کاملFunctions and Features of the Residential Spaces Matching Children’s Needs
The houses which are not suitable for children’s behavioral needs and are not proportionate to their cognitive patterns cannot play a significant role in reinforcing children’s physical and mental development process. Meanwhile, living in these houses is inevitable due to numerous reasons including economy. The extreme results of this form of life can lead to ...
متن کاملThe Necessity of Conservation and Restoration in Modern Axiological Approach to Historic Monuments
Any monument that is deemed competent for conservation and restoration, is bringing the values of their creation time and then. Thus with any work which is conserved and restored, in fact, the culture and civilization is maintained. Because of the intrinsic link between “history” and “conservation”, it is necessary to reflect on related factors to the restoration, and the importance and necessi...
متن کامل